Sunday, March 15, 2009

Polish Prof. Boguslaw Wolniewicz on the Formal Ontology of Situations

Polish Prof. Boguslaw Wolniewicz on the Formal Ontology of Situations



INTRODUCTION
"The theory presented below was developed in an effort to clarify the metaphysics of Wittgenstein's Tractatus. The result obtained, however, is not strictly the formal twin of his variant of Logical Atomism. but something more, general, of which the latter is lust a special case. One might call it an ontology of situations. Some basic ideas of that ontology stern from Stenius Wittgenstein's Tractatus, Oxford, 1968 and Suszko Ontology in the Tractatus of L. Wittgenstein - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 1968.
Let L be a classic propositional language. Propositions of L are supposed to have their semantic counterparts in the realm of possibility, or as Wittgenstein put it: in logical space. These counterparts are situations, and S is to be the totality of them. The situation described by a proposition a is S(a). With Meinong we call it the objective of a."
From: Boguslaw Wolniewicz - A formal ontology of situations - Studia Logica 41: 381-413 (1982). pp. 381-382.

"Different ontologies adopt different notions of existence as basic. Aristotle's paradigm of existence is given by the equivalence:
(A) to be = to be a substance.
On the other hand, the paradigm of existence adopted in Wittgenstein's Tractatus is given by the parallel equivalence:
(W) to be = to be a fact.
Now, an Aristotelian substance is the denotation of an individual name, whereas a Wittgensteinian fact is the denotation of a true proposition. It seems therefore that the notions of existence derived from these two paradigms should be quite different, and one might readily expect that the metaphysical systems erected upon them will display wide structural discrepancies.
It turns out, however, that in spite of this basic difference there runs between these two systems a deep and striking parallelism. This parallelism is so close indeed that it makes possible the construction of a vocabulary which would transform characteristic propositions of Wittgenstein's ontology into Aristotelian ones, and conversely. To show in some detail the workings of that transformation will be the subject of this paper.
The vocabulary mentioned is based on the following four fundamental correlations:

Aristotle
1) primary substances (substantiae primae)
2) prime matter (materia prima)
3) form (forma)
4) self-subsistence of primary substances (esse per se)

Wittgenstein
1) atomic facts
2) objects
3) confiugration
4) independence of atomic facts

Aristotle's ontology is an ontology of substances, Wittgenstein's ontology is an ontology of facts. But concerning the respective items of each of the pairs (1)-(4) both ontologies lay down conditions which in view of our vocabulary appear to be identical. To show this let us confront, to begin with, the items of pair (1): substances and facts.
(The interpretation of Aristotle adopted in this paper is the standard one, to be found in any competent textbook of the history of philosophy. Therefore, with but one exception, no references to Aristotle's works will be given here.)Relatively to the system involved substances and facts are of the same ontological status. Aristotle's world is the totality of substances (summa rerum), Wittgenstein's world is the totality of facts (die Gesamtheit der Tatsachen). For Aristotle whatever exists in the basic sense of the word is a primary substance, for Wittgenstein - an atomic fact. Moreover, both ontologies are MODAL ones, allowing for different modes of being (modi essendi); and both take as basic the notion of `contingent being' (esse contingens), opposed to necessary being on the one hand, and to the possibility of being on the other. Both substances and facts are entities which actually exist, but might have not existed. The equality of ontological status between substances and facts is corroborated by the circumstance that both are PARTICULARS, there being - as the saying goes - no multiplicity of entities which FALL UNDER them.
Substances and facts stand also in the same relation to the ontological categories of pairs (2) and (3). Both are always COMPOUND entities, a substance consisting of matter and form, and a fact consisting of objects and the way of their configuration. But in neither of the two systems is this compoundness to be understood literally as composition of physically separable parts or pieces. The compoundness (compositio) of a substance consists in its being formed stuff (materia informata), and the compoundness of a fact in its being a configuration of objects.
In view of correlation (4) we have also an equality of relation which a substance bears to other substances, and a fact to other facts. Self-subsistence is the characteristic attribute of primary substances: substantia prima = ens per se. If we take this to mean that each substance exists independently of the existence or non-existence of any other substance we get immediately the exact counterpart of Wittgenstein's principle of logical atomism stating the mutual independence of atomic facts. It should be noted that thus understood the attribute of self-subsistence or independence is a relative one, belonging to a substance - or to a fact - only in virtue of its relation to other substances - or facts.
From a Wittgensteinian point of view Aristotle's substances are not things, but hypostases of facts, and thus their names are not logically proper names, but name-like equivalents of propositions. (By that term we mean roughly either a noun clause of the form `that p', or any symbol which might be regarded as a definitional abbreviation of such clause.) Surely, from the Aristotelian point of view it might be easily retorted here that just the opposite is the case: substances are not `reified' facts, but on the contrary - facts are 'dereified' substances. Without passing judgement on these mutual objections let us note in passing that their symmetric character seems to be itself an additional manifestation of the parallelism discussed."
From: Boguslaw Wolniewicz - A parallelism between Wittgensteinian and Aristotelian ontologies. In Boston studies in the philosophy of science. Vol. IV. Edited by Cohen Robert S. and Wartofsky Marx W. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company 1969. pp. 208-210 (notes omitted).

SELECTED PUBLICATIONS (Works in Polish are not enclosed)
In 1970 Boguslaw Wolniewicz published a Polish translation of Ludwig Wittgenstein Tractatus logico-philosophicus.

A difference between Russell's and Wittgenstein's logical atomism. In Akten des XIV. Internationalen Kongresses für Philosophie. Wien, 2. - 9. September 1968 - Vol. II. Wien: Herder 1968. pp. 263-267Reprinted in: Logic and metaphysics (1999) - pp.193-197

"A note on Black's 'Companion'," Mind 78: 141 (1969).Reprinted in: Logic and metaphysics (1999) - p. 229."It is a mistake to suppose that in Wittgenstein's "Tractatus" the meaning of Urbild has any connexion with that of picture. "

A parallelism between Wittgensteinian and Aristotelian ontologies. In Boston studies in the philosophy of science. Vol. IV. Edited by Cohen Robert S. and Wartofsky Marx W. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company 1969. pp. 208-217Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the philosophy of science 1966/1968.Reprinted in: Logic and metaphysics (1999) - pp.198-207

"Four notion of independence," Theoria 36: 161-164 (1970).Reprinted in: Logic and metaphysics (1999) - pp.127-130.WFour (binary) relations of independence I(p,q) between propositions are distinguished: the Wittgensteinian I sub-w, the statistical I sub-s, the modal I sub-m, and the deductive I sub-d. The validity of the following theorem is argued for: I sub-w(p,q) implies I sub-s(p,q) implies I sub-m(p,q) implies Isub-d(p,q). "

Wittgensteinian foundations of non-Fregean logic. In Contemporary East European philosophy. Vol. 3. Edited by D'Angelo Edward, DeGrood David, and Riepe Dale. Bridgeport: Spartacus Books 1971. pp. 231-243

"The notion of fact as a modal operator," Teorema: 59-66 (1972).Reprinted in: Logic and metaphysics (1999) - pp. 218-224"The notion of fact /fp = "it is a fact that p"/ is characterized axiomatically, and the ensuing modal systems shown to be equivalent to tT, S4 and S5 respectively."

Zur Semantik des Satzkalküls: Frege und Wittgenstein. In Der Mensch - Subjekt und Objekt (Festchrift für Adam Schaff). Edited by Borbé Tasso. Wien: Europaverl. 1973. pp.

Sachlage und Elementarsätz. In Wittgenstein and his impact on contemporary thought. Proceedings of the Second International Wittgenstein Symposium, 29th August to 4th September 1977, Kirchberg/Wechsel (Austria). Edited by Leinfellner Elisabeth. Wien: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky 1977. pp. 174-176

"Objectives of propositions," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 7: 143-147 (1978)."The paper sketches out a semantics for propositions based upon the Wittgensteinian notion of a possible situation. The objective of a proposition is defined as the smallest situation verifying it. Two propositions are assumed to have the same objective iff they are strictly equivalent. Formulas are given which determine the objectives of conjunction and disjunction as functions of the objectives of their components. finally a link with possible-world semantics is established."

"Situations as the reference of propositions," Dialectics and Humanism 5: 171-182 (1978)."The reference of propositions is determined for a class of languages to be called the "Wittgensteinian" ones. A meaningful proposition presents a possible situation. Every consistent conjunction of elementary propositions presents an elementary situation. The smallest elementary situations are the "Sachverhalte"; the greatest are possible worlds. The situation presented by a proposition is to be distinguished from that verifying it, but the greatest situation presented is identical with the smallest verifying. The reference of compound propositions is then determined as a function of their components."

"Les situations comme corrélats semantiques des enoncés," Studia Filozoficzne 2: 27-41 (1978).

Wittgenstein und der Positivismus. In Wittgenstein, the Vienna circle and critical rationalism. Proceedings of the third International Wittgenstein Symposium, 13th to 19th August 1978, Kirchberg am Wechsel (Austria). Edited by Bergehel Hal, Hübner Adolf, and Eckehart Köhler. Wien: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky 1978. pp. 75-77

"Some formal properties of objectives," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 8: 16-20 (1979)."The objectives of propositions as defined in an earlier paper are shown here to form a distributive lattice."

A Wittgensteinian semantics for propositions. In Intention and intentionality. Essay in honour of G. E. M. Anscombe. Edited by Diamond Cora and Teichman Jenny. Ithaca: Cornell University Press 1979. pp. 165-178"More than once Professor Anscombe has expressed doubt concerning the semantic efficacy of the idea of an 'elementary proposition' as conceived in the Tractatus. Wittgenstein himself eventually discarded it, together with the whole philosophy of language of which it had been an essential part. None the less the idea is still with us, and it seems to cover theoretical potentialities yet to be explored. This paper is a tentative move in that direction.According to Professor Anscombe, (*) Wittgenstein's 'elementary propositions' may be characterized by the following five theses: (1) They are a class of mutually independent propositions.(2) They are essentially positive.(2) They are such that for each of them there are no two ways of being true or false, but only one.(4) They are such that there is in them no distinction between an internal and an external negation.(5) They are concatenations of names, which are absolutely simple signs.We shall not investigate whether this is an adequate axiomatic for the notion under consideration. We suppose it is. In any case it is possible to modify it in one way or another, and for the resulting notion still to preserve a family resemblance with the original idea. One such modification is sketched out below."

"On the lattice of elementary situations," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 9: 115-121 (1980).

"On the verifiers of disjunction," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 9: 57-59 (1980).

"The Boolean algebra of objectives," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 10: 17-23 (1981)."This concludes a series of papers constructing a semantics for propositional languages based on the notion of a possible "situation". Objectives of propositions are the situations described by them. The set of objectives is defined and shown to be a boolean algebra isomorphic to that formed by sets of possible worlds."

"A closure system for elementary situations," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 11: 134-139 (1982).

"On logical space," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 11: 84-88 (1982).

"Ludwig Fleck and Polish philosophy," Dialectics and Humanism 9: 25-28 (1982).

"A formal ontology of situations," Studia Logica 41: 381-413 (1982)."A generalized Wittgensteinian semantics for propositional languages is presented, based on a lattice of elementary situations. Of these, maximal ones are possible worlds, constituting a logical space; minimal ones are logical atoms, partitioned into its dimensions. A verifier of a proposition is an elementary situation such that if real it makes true. The reference (or objective) of a proposition is a situation, which is the set of all its minimal verifiers. (Maximal ones constitute its locus.) Situations are shown to form a Boolean algebra, and the Boolean set algebra of loci is its representation. Wittgenstein's is a special case, admitting binary dimensions only."Contents:0. Preliminaries; 1. Elementary Situations1.1.The Axioms; 1.2.Some Consequences; 1.3. W-Independence; 1.4.States of Affairs;2. Sets of Elementary Situations2.1.The Semigroup of SE"-Sets; 2.2.The Lattice of Minimal SE"-Sets; 2.3.Q-Spaces and V-Sets; 2.4.V-Equivalence and Q-Equivalence; 2.4.V-Classes and V-Sets;3. Objectives of Propositions3.1. Verifiers of Propositions; 3.2. Verifying and Forcing; 3.3. Situations and Logical Loci; 3.4. Loci and Objectives of Compound Propositions 3.5. The Boolean Algebra of Situations;4. References

"Truth arguments and independence," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 12: 21-28 (1983).

"Logical space and metaphysical systems," Studia Logica 42: 269-284 (1983)."The paper applies the theory presented in "A formal ontology of situations" (Studia Logica, vol. 41 (1982), no. 4) to obtain a typology of metaphysical systems by interpreting them as different ontologies of situations.Four are treated in some detail: Hume's diachronic atomism, Laplacean determinism, Hume's synchronic atomism, and Wittgenstein's logical atomism. Moreover, the relation of that theory to the "situation semantics" of Perry and Barwise is discussed."

"An algebra of subsets for join-semilatttices with unit," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 13: 21-24 (1984).

"A topology for logical space," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 13: 255-259 (1984).

"Suszko: a reminiscence," Studia Logica 43: 317-321 (1984).Reprinted in: Logic and metaphysics (1999) - pp.302-306

"Die Grundwerte einer wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassaung," Conceptus 19: 3-8 (1985)."The scientific world-view is one of the fundamentals of our culture. It can be characterized in part by its specific system of values. A world-view is regarded as a scientific one if "truth" is one of its primary values, that is, as a value which is not a means, but an end in itself. Truth is served in particular by the two instrumental values of conceptual clarity and openness to critique. Their standing is (at present) low, for two reasons. (1) Unclear thinking not only promotes social idols; its consequences are also often difficult to see clearly and immediately. (2) In any case truth is of no interest (in a biological sense) to human beings; therefore, critique can at best be a socially tolerated activity. On the other hand, truth is not only a value, but also a force which in the long run cannot be held back; this fact gives some hope to adherents of the scientific world-view. "

"Discreteness of logical space," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 15: 132-136 (1986).

"Entailments and independence in join-semilattices," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 18: 2-5 (1989)."The paper generalizes Wittgenstein's notion of independence. in a join-semilattice of elementary situations the atoms are the Sachverhalte, and maximal ideals are possible worlds. A subset of that semilattice is independent iff it is free of "ontic ties". This is shown to be equivalent to independence in von Neumann's sense."

"On atomic join-semilattices," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 18: 105-111 (1989).Reprinted in: Logic and metaphysics (1999) - pp. 307-312.
The essence of Logical Atomism: Hume and Wittgenstein. In Wittgenstein. Eine Neubewertung. Akten 14. Internationale Wittgenstein-Symposium. Vol. 1. Wien: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky 1990. pp. 106-111

"A question about join-semilattices," Bulletin of the Section of Logic: 108 (1990).

Concerning reism in Kotarbinski. In Kotarbinski: logic. semantics and ontology. Edited by Wolenski Jan. Dordrecht: Kluwer 1990. pp. 199-204Reprinted in: Logic and metaphysics (1999) - pp.265-271

Elzenberg's logic of values. In Logic counts. Edited by Zarnecka-Bialy Ewa. Dordrecht: Kluwe 1990. pp. 63-70Reprinted in: Logic and metaphysics (1999) - pp. 286-292 (with the title: Elzenberg's axiology""1. Values are what our value-Judgements refer to, and the passing of Judgements is one of our vital activities, like sleeping and breathing. We constantly appraise things as good or bad, pretty or ugly, as noble or base, well-made or misshapen. No wonder that both the act of appraisal and that which it refers to - i.e. the real or spurious values - have been always the source of philosophical reflexion. In systematic form such reflexion is what we call axiology.In Polish philosophy it was Henryk Elzenberg (1887-1967) who reflected upon matters of axiology most deeply and incisively.(...)3. Leibniz had said somewhere: "There are two mazes in which the human mind is most likely to get lost: one is the concept of continuity, the other is that of liberty". This admits of generalization: all concepts are mazes, viz mazes of logical relations between the propositions that involve them.One such maze is the concept of 'value'. Possibly, it is even the same as one of the two mentioned by Leibniz, only entered - so to say - by another door. For it would be in full accord with Elzenberg's position - and with that of Kant too - to adopt the following characteristic: values are what controls the actions of free agents. Thus the concepts of value and of liberty should constitute one conceptual maze, or - which comes to the same - two mazes communicating with each other.To get a survey of such logical maze the first thing is to fix the ontological category of the concept in question. Thus, in our case, we ask what kind of entities are those 'values' supposed to be. (Ontological categories are the most general classes of entities, the summa genera A term even more general has to cover literally everything: like 'entity' or 'something'. For everything is an entity, just as everything is a something.)Different ontologies admit different sets of categories. The categories most frequently referred to are those of 'objects', 'properties', and 'relations'; the more exotic ones are those of an 'event', a 'set', a 'function', or a 'situation'. One point, however, is of paramount importance: the categories admitted In one ontology have to be mutually disjoint". p. 63; 66.

"A sequel to Hawranek/Zygmunt," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 20: 143-144 (1991).

Needs and value. In Logic and ethics. Edited by Geach Peter. Dordrecht: Kluwer 1991. pp.

On the discontinuity of Wittgenstein's philosophy. In Peter Geach: philosophical encounters. Edited by Lewis Harry. Dordrecht: Kluwer 1991. pp. 77-81Reprinted in: Logic and metaphysics (1999) - pp. 13-17.

"A question of logic in the philosophy of religion," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 22: 33-36 (1993).

On the synthetic a priori. In Philosophical logic in Poland. Edited by Wolenski Jan. Dordrecht: Kluwer 1994. pp. 327-336

Logic and metaphysics. Studies in Wittgenstein's ontology of facts. Warsaw: Polskie Towarzystwo Semiotyczne 1999.Contents: Preface 11; Discontinuity of Wittgenstein's philosophy 13; 1. Elementary situations as a lattice of finite length 19; Elementary situations as a semilattice 73; 3. Independence 127; 4. Elementary situations generalized 137; 5. Auxiliary studies 193; 5.1 The Logical Atomisms of Russell and Wittgenstein 193; 5.2 A parallelism between Wittgenstein and Aristotle 198; 5.3 Frege's semantics 207; 5.4. The notion of fact as a modal operator 218; 5.5 "Tractatus" 5.541 - 5.542 224; 5.6 History of the concept of a Situation 229; 6. Offshoots 243 6.1 Languages and codes 243; 6.2 Logic and hermeneutics 254; 6.3 Kotarbinski's Reism 265; 6.4 On Bayle's critique of theodicy 271; 6.5 Elzenberg's axiology 286; 6.6 Needs and values 293; 6.7 Suszko: a reminiscence 302; Supplements 307; Indices: Index of subjects 317; Index of names 326; Index of Tractatus references 329.

"Atoms in semantic frames," Logica Trianguli 4: 69-86 (2000)."Elaborating on Wittgenstein's ontology of facts, semantic frames are described axiomatically as based on the notion of an elementary situation being the verifier of a proposition. Conditions are investigated then for suchframes to be atomic, i.e. to have lattice-theoretic counterparts of his "Sachverhalte"."

"Extending atomistic frames," Logica Trianguli 5 (2001)."A "semantic frame" is bounded join-semilattice of elementary situations, with its maximal ideals to represent possible worlds and mapped into the complete sets of propositions determined by a given abstract logic (L, Cn). A frame is Humean if the elementary situations are separated by its possible worlds, and it is atomistic if the semilattice is so. One frame is the extension of another if the latter is an {0,1}-subsemilattice of the former satisfying certain conditions discussed."

Tractatus 5.541 - 5.542. In Satz un Sachverhalt. Edited by Neumaier Otto. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag 2001. pp. 185-190"In Wittgenstein's "Tractatus", thesis 5 is the Principle of Extensionality: all propositions are truth-functions of their clauses. This, however, has been often thrown into doubt. There are - it is said - compound propositions whose truth-value does not depend on that of their clauses. The usual example given are the so-called intensional contexts, like "John thinks that p", or "John says that p". And indeed, the truth-value of "p" is patently immaterial here to that of the whole proposition which it is part of.Wittgenstein's retort are the following much discussed theses, adduced here in a translation of our own:5.54 In the general propositional form, propositions occur in one another only as bases of truth-operations.5.541 At first sight it seems that a proposition might occur in another also in a different way.Particularly in certain propositional forms of psychology, like "A believes that p is the case", "A thinks p", etc.For taken superficially, proposition p seems here to stand to the object A in some sort of relation.(And in modem epistemology - Russell, Moore, etc. - these have actually been construed that way.)5.542 However, "A believes that p", "A thinks p", "A says p" are clearly of the form " 'p' says p "; and this is not correlating a fact with an object, but a correlation of facts by correlating their objects.The objection is met here in two steps. Firstly, it is pointed out that a proposition of the form "John says that p" is actually of the form "'p' says that p". The idea is this: the proposition "John says that Jill has a cat" means: John produces the sentence "Jill has a cat", the latter saying by itself that Jill has a cat. In such a way propositions get independent of the persons producing them, and communicate some objective content. It is surely not by John's looks that we come to know about Jill's cat, but merely by his words. Whom they stem from, is irrelevant.In his second step Wittgenstein follows Frege's interpretation of indirect speech, but with modifications. He points out that the formula " 'p' says that p " is equivalent to some compound proposition in which neither the proposition "p" as a syntactic unit, nor anything equivalent to it, does occur although there occur all the logically relevant constituents of "p" separately.(...)The distinction between abstract and concrete states of affairs is not drawn explicitly in the "Tractatus". But it fits well thesis 5.156, if we expand that thesis by a few words of comment, added here in brackets:5.156(d) A proposition may well be en incomplete image of a particular (concrete) situation, but it is always the complete image (of an abstract one).The circumstance that in 5.156 not "states of affairs", but "situations" are mentioned, is of no consequence in our context. We assume that states of affairs are just atomic situations, and so the distinction between "concrete" and "abstract" applies to both."

"Extending atomistic frames: part II," Logica Trianguli 6: 69-88 (2003)."The paper concludes an earlier one (Logica Trianguli, 5) on extensions of atomistic semantic frames. Three kinds of extension are considered: the adjunctive, the conjunctive, and the disjunctive one. Some theorems are proved on extending "Humean" frames, i.e. such that the elementary situations constituting their universa are separated by the maximally coherent sets of them ("realizations")."

"On a minimality condition," Bulletin of the Section of Logic 34: 227-228 (2005).


Alex BajanRAQport Inc.2004 North Monroe StreetArlington Virginia 22207Washington DC AreaUSATEL: 703-528-0114TEL2: 703-652-0993FAX: 202-318-4021sms/cell T-mobile: 703-485-6619EMAIL: office@raqport.comor alex@raqport.comWEB SITE: http://raqport.com

Saturday, March 14, 2009

Myśląc Ojczyzna: " Oczekując na wyjaśnienia"

Myśląc Ojczyzna: " Oczekując na wyjaśnienia"
red. Stanisław Michalkiewicz (2009-03-11)
Felieton
słuchajzapisz

Szanowni Państwo!

Przed kilkoma dniami Rzecznik Paw Obywatelskich, pan doktor Janusz Kochanowski, zażądał wyjaśnień od ministra ochrony środowiska, jakie były prawdziwe przyczyny odmowy dofinansowania ze środków publicznych wierceń geotermalnych, prowadzonych przez Fundację Lux Veritatis, a także wyjasnień od ministra spraw wewnętrznych, jakie były prawdziwe przyczyny odmowy zgody na zbiórkę publiczną w celu sfinansowania tych wierceń.
Jak pamiętamy, obydwa urzędy wprawdzie uzasadniły swoje decyzje, ale Rzecznik Praw Obywatelskich musiał nabrać podejrzeń co do prawdziwości tych uzasadnień, skoro zażądał wyjaśnień. Do takich podejrzeń miał wystarczające podstawy, ponieważ tajemnicą poliszynela jest, iż zarówno jednak, jak i druga odmowa, były podyktowane względami politycznymi i to w dodatku - podwójnymi.
Po pierwsze - chodziło o wykorzystanie każdej okazji do stworzenia Fundacji Lux Veritatis trudności finansowych w nadziei, że te trudności doprowadzą do upadku Radia Maryja i Telewizji Trwam. Likwidacja zaś Radia Maryja i Telewizji Trwam pozostaje jednym z dwóch głównych celów loży B`nai B`rith, a także - niektórych państw. Ponieważ wielu urzędników państwowych, również urzędników wysokiego szczebla, jest szczegółlnie podatnych na rozmaite zachęty i naciski, więc jest wysoce prawdopodobne, że taka właśnie sytuacja miała miejsce w przypadku wniosków złożonych przez Fundację Lux Veritatis.
Po drugie - kierownictwu Platformy Obywatelskiej chodziło również o udelektowanie tych środowisk, których poparcie przywiodło ją do zewnętrznych znamion władzy. Nie jest żadną tajemnicą, że najbardziej wpływowym środowiskiem jest komunistyczna razwiedka, zarówno ubecja cywilna, jak i wojskowa. Kto raz był królem, zawsze zachowa majestat. Czym skorupka za młodu nasiąknie, tym na starość śmierdzi, więc nic dziwnego, że bezpieczniacy, którzy zgodnie z leninowskimi normami traktowali Kościół jako wroga przeznaczonego do zniszczenia, obecnie całą swoją furię obrócili na toruńską rozgłośnię.
Ale dla Rzecznika Praw Obywatelskich te resentymenty starych torturantów nie są dostatecznym argumentem. Powołując się na zasadę równości obywateli wobec prawa, zażądał od obydwu dygnitarzy wyjaśnień i miejmy nadzieję, że tym razem będą one prawdziwe, to znaczy - że przedstawią rzeczywiste powody odmownych decyzji, a nie tylko preteksty.
W oczekiwaniu na te wyjaśnienia zwróćmy jednak uwagę na sprawy ogólniejsze, a przede wszystkim na to, czy biurokracja nie usurpowała sobie aby zbyt dużej władzy nad nami.
Co ministrowi Schetynie do tego, że jeden człowiek, albo niechby i milion ludzi, chce przekazać innemu człowiekowi swoje własne pieniądze i to nie na żaden cel przestępczy, tylko całkowicie zgodny z prawem, a nawet - potencjalnie pożyteczny dla ogółu? Zdrowy rozsądek i poczucie sprawiedliwości podpowiada nam, że ministrowi Schetynie nic do tego. My zresztą też nie żądamy od niego, żeby się przed nami tłumaczył, co robi z własnymi pieniędzmi. To jego prywatna sprawa. Co innego, gdy wydaje pieniądze publiczne. Ale prywatne osoby nie będące żadnymi dygnitarzami, ani funkcjonariuszami publicznymi, nie dysponują publicznymi pieniędzmi, tylko własnymi. Co z nimi robią i komu je dają - to ich sprawa i żadnemu ministrowi nic do tego.
Niestety biurokraci uważają inaczej. Uważają, że mogą się wtrącać w nasze prywatne sprawy i te uroszczenia ubierają w pozory legalności. Takim pozorem legalności jest ustawa z 15 marca 1933 roku o zbiórkach publicznych, która w artykule pierwszym ustanawia uzurpatorską zasadę, że "wszelkie publiczne zbieranie ofiar w gotówce lub w naturze na pewien z góry określony cel, wymaga uprzedniego zezwolenia władzy". Dlaczego? Ano - dlatego, że władza lubi, żeby ją prosić, a ona może zezwolić, albo nie. Zwróćmy uwagę, że jest to ustawa przedwojenna, z 1933 roku. Hydra biurokratyczna występowała już wtedy, ale oczywiście od tamtej pory rozrosła się do rozmiarów monstrualnych. Warto pamiętać, ze rozrasta się ona i rozszerza zakres swojej władzy kosztem naszej wolności i naszych pieniędzy. Im więcej wolno wladzy - tym mniej wolno nam. Im więcej urzędników - tym więcej pieniędzy musimy trwonić na ich utrzymanie, zaś pożytku z nich mamy tyle, co pies z piątej nogi.
Rzecznik Praw Obywatelskich też zwrócił na to uwagę, pisząc, że ustawa o zbiórkach publicznych jest anachroniczna i nie przystaje do realiów gospodarki rynkowej. Ale ustawa o zbiórkach publicznych może być też sprzeczna z konstytucją, a konkretnie - z artykułem 64 ustęp 3. Mówi on, że "własność może być ograniczona tylko w drodze ustawy i tylko w zakresie, w jakim nie narusza ona istoty prawa własności".
Do istoty prawa własności należy między innymi swobodne rozporządzanie rzeczą, a więc - swobodne rozporządzanie własnymi pieniędzmi. Jeśli zatem chcę moje własne pieniądze przekazać innemu człowiekowi, to nie powinienem być zmuszany do proszenia trzeciego człowieka, który do moich pieniędzy nie ma żadnego prawa, o pozwolenie. Zatem - jedyną przeszkodą w przeprowadzeniu zbiórki publicznej może być jej nielegalność, to znaczy - gdyby jej cel był przestępstwem. Na przykład - gdybyśmy zaczęli zbierac pieniądze, żeby opłacić zawodowego mordercę, by zastrzelił pana ministra Schetynę. Ale jeśli zbiórce żaden przestępczy cel nie towarzyszy, to niczyje zezwolenie nie powinno być potrzebne.

Miejmy nadzieję, że interwencja Rzecznika Praw Obywatelskich doprowadzi do zmiany decyzji obydwu ministerstw w sprawie wniosków Fundacji Lux Veritatis. Byłoby jeszcze lepiej, gdyby ta interwencja doprowadziła do uchylenia ustawy z 15 marca 1933 roku o zbiórkach publicznych - a także wielu innych, podobnych ustaw i przepisów. Byłoby to piękne - ale obawiam się, że zbyt piękne, aby było prawdziwe. Biurokracja, ci nasi okupanci, dobrowolnie nie zrezygnują ani ze swojej władzy, ani ze swoich dochodów. Nie pozwoli im na to ich pycha oraz ich chciwość. Dlatego musimy stale na nich naciskać, musimy wytrwale bronić naszej wolności, bo jeśli tylko choć na chwilę przestaniemy, to zrobią z nas niewolników.
Mówił Stanisław Michalkiewicz


Klania sie Lech Bajan z Waszyngtonu z apelem o pomoc finansowa!

dla Projektu Polskiej Geotermii - Polskiej Energii Odnawialnej prowadzonej przez Radio Maryja

Konta bankowe Radia Maryja
Konta złotówkowe
- PKO BP S.A. II/O Toruń
nr 69 1020 5011 0000 9602 0012 9130
- Bank Pocztowy S.A. O/Toruń
nr 77 1320 1120 2565 1113 2000 0003
z dopiskiem: "Dar na cele kultu religijnego"
Konta walutowe
EUR - PKO BP S.A. II/O Toruń
ul. Grudziądzka 4, 87-100 Toruń
nr 65 1020 5011 0000 9602 0105 7298
Funty GBP - PKO BP S.A. II/O Toruń
ul. Grudziądzka 4, 87-100 Toruń
nr 08 1020 5011 0000 9502 0105 7306
Dolary USD - PKO BP S.A. II/O Toruń
ul. Grudziądzka 4, 87-100 Toruń
nr 13 1020 5011 0000 9302 0105 7314
(Ofiarodawcy spoza Polski przed numerem konta winni dopisać symbol PL, a po numerze: SWIFT - BPKOPLPW)

Konto w USA
RADIO MARYJA, P.O. BOX 39565
CHICAGO, IL 60639-0565

Konto w Kanadzie
St. Stanislaus - St. Casimir's Polish Parishes - Credit Union Limited
40 John St., Oakville, ONT L6K 1G8
Numer konta: 84920

Friday, March 13, 2009

Lekcja prezesa Cato Institute dla prezydenta Polski

Lekcja prezesa Cato Institute dla prezydenta Polski


Chodzi o ważną lekcję udzieloną przez Teda Galena Carpentera, prezesa prestiżowego Cato Institute w Waszyngtonie, szefa wydziału obrony i polityki zagranicznej oraz autora ośmiu książek dotyczących stosunków międzynarodowych, prezydentowi Polski, Lechowi Kaczyńskiemu. Prezydent Kaczyński wystąpił przed kamerami telewizji TVN24, wyrażając swoje głębokie rozczarowanie z powodu upadku projektu budowy wyrzutni rakiet amerykańskich typu „Tarcza” w Polsce. Stanowisko profesora Carpentera w tej sprawie można znaleźć artykule pod tytułem The Limits of Deterrence (Granice odstraszania) z 3 września 2008 roku.

Tłem obecnej sytuacji międzynarodowej jest gwarantowane obopólne zniszczenie nuklearne Rosji i USA na wypadek konfliktu między tymi państwami. Biorąc to pod uwagę, profesor Carpenter pisze, że gwarancje bezpieczeństwa, obiecywane przez USA 50 państwom, są dokładnie tyle warte, co czeki bez pokrycia. Przypomina to gwarancje dane Polsce w 1939 roku przez Brytyjczyków i Francuzów, które nie spowodowały włączenia się tych państw w akcje przeciwko agresorowi niemieckiemu, który napadł na sojuszniczą Polskę.

Fakt, że USA mają bez porównania większą gospodarkę niż Rosja, traci znaczenie wobec równowagi siły niszczącej ich arsenałów. Poza tym ważną sprawą jest nierówny ciężar gatunkowy sprawy „Tarczy” dla USA i Rosji. Dla Stanów Zjednoczonych posiadanie rakiet w Polsce, o kilka minut lotu pocisku od Moskwy, jest atrakcyjnym manewrem strategicznym, z użyciem polskiego pionka, który można poświęcić w razie grożących mu rosyjskich bomb nuklearnych.

Natomiast dla Rosji szachowanie przez USA rakietami ustawionymi blisko rosyjskich ośrodków dowodzenia i kontroli jest czymś bez porównania bardziej nie do zaakceptowania, niż było dla USA stawianie sowieckich wyrzutni rakiet na Kubie w 1962 roku, gdzie odległość ich od Waszyngtonu była dwa razy większa, niż planowanych wyrzutni „Tarczy” w Polsce od Moskwy.

Obecną sytuację opisał Ryan Lucas z Associated Press, 8 marca 2009 roku, w artykule pod tytułem Polish President: Missile defense should go ahead; Polish President: US decision against missile defense would be unfriendly gesture. (Prezydent Polski twierdzi: należy budować w Polsce wyrzutnie rakiet Tarczy; Polski prezydent twierdzi, że decyzja USA przeciwko budowie wyrzutni rakiet Tarczy byłaby nieprzyjaznym gestem). Tego rodzaju wypowiedzi prezydenta Polski kompromitują go w oczach wszystkich ludzi, rozumiejących obecną grę strategiczną między USA i Rosją.

Prezydent Obama napisał ostatnio do prezydenta Rosji, Dymitra Miedwiediewa, że w zamian za rosyjską pomoc w ograniczaniu programu nuklearnego Iranu, gotów jest zrezygnować z budowy wyrzutni rakiet „Tarcza” w Polsce. Nie ulega najmniejszej wątpliwości, że gdyby Rosjanie zbombardowali Polskę bombami nuklearnymi z powodu potencjalnego zagrożenia Moskwy nuklearnymi pociskami „Tarczy”, Waszyngton w żadnym razie nie użyłby bomb nuklearnych przeciwko Rosji, ponieważ chodzi mu głównie o uniknięcie rosyjskiego ataku nuklearnego na teren USA. Natomiast prezydent Polski całkowicie niepotrzebnie naraża swój kraj, przy okazji zamrażając kontrakty na dostawy polskiej żywności do Rosji, z korzyścią dla innych członków NATO i UE.

Równowaga terroru nuklearnego arsenałów USA i Rosji idzie w parze z tym, jakie znaczenie ma dana sprawa dla każdej z superpotęg nuklearnych. Zachodnia Europa w czasie „zimnej wojny” miała bez porównania większe strategiczne znaczenie dla USA niż dla Sowietów i dlatego wówczas USA były gotowe obrócić Polskę w strefę zatrutą radioaktywnie za pomocą bombardowania nuklearnego, w celu zablokowania dostępu z ZSRR do Europy Zachodniej. W latach 70. XX wieku bronił Polski pułkownik Ryszard Kukliński, uniemożliwiając Sowietom przygotowanie niespodziewanego ataku na Zachód, przez przekazanie CIA kilkudziesięciu tysięcy dokumentów sztabu Paktu Warszawskiego.

Pamiętamy, jak zaciekły syjonista Winston Churchill zdradził Polskę w Teheranie w 1943 roku, a w roku 1944 powiedział Stalinowi, że losy Polski i Polaków mało go obchodzą. Chodziło mu tylko o zachowanie pozorów, o to, by wybory w Polsce znajdującej się pod sowiecką okupacją nie były skandalicznym fałszerstwem, potępionym przez opinię światową i eksponującym zdradę polskiego sojusznika przez jej brytyjskiego sprzymierzeńca.

Obecnie zarówno państwa bałtyckie, jak i Polska, niby zabezpieczone gwarancjami NATO, faktycznie łudzą się, zdaniem profesora Carpentera, ponieważ gwarancje te są blefem, a nie odbiciem faktycznego znaczenia owych państw dla USA. Są prawdziwymi „czekami bez pokrycia”, kompromitującymi polityków, którzy albo naiwnie wierzą w te gwarancje, albo perfidnie wysługują się obcym interesom kosztem własnej ojczyzny.

Niestety, prezydent Kaczyński jest „recydywistą”, ponieważ wcześniej, jako ówczesny minister sprawiedliwości i prokurator generalny, podpisał rozkaz przerwania ekshumacji w Jedwabnem, kiedy chodziło o ustalenie, ile osób zostało tam zamordowanych i w jaki sposób ludzie ci stracili życie. Oszuści z żydowskiego ruchu roszczeniowego, posługując się oszukańczą książką J. T. Grossa Sąsiedzi, sugerowali, że zwłoki tych Żydów, którzy nieśli rozbity pomnik Lenina, zostały pochowane na kirkucie, czyli żydowskim cmentarzu, a nie w stodole, gdzie się faktycznie znalazły po zastrzeleniu tych ludzi przez Niemców. Działo się to podczas niemieckiej okupacji, kiedy broń palna była dla Polaków absolutnie niedostępna, co zresztą potwierdza nawet Gross.

Perfidia Grossa polegała na kłamstwie, mającym na celu niedopuszczenie polskich badaczy medycyny sądowej do ustalenia, że ludzie, którzy nieśli rozbity pomnik Lenina, zostali zastrzeleni przez Niemców w stodole, po wykopaniu przez nich dołu w klepisku. Niemcy użyli około 400 litrów benzyny, żeby stodoła stanęła w ogniu. Ówczesny rabin Warszawy i Łodzi (obecny naczelny rabin Polski) Michael Schudrich skutecznie interweniował u Kaczyńskiego, żeby nie dopuścić do całkowitej kompromitacji oszustów z żydowskiego ruchu roszczeniowego, którzy fałszywie oskarżają Polaków, a jednocześnie bogacą się nieustannie, przejmując sumy odszkodowań np. ze strony banków szwajcarskich dla ofiar holokaustu.

Oszuści z żydowskiego ruchu roszczeniowego przywłaszczają sobie odszkodowania należne żydowskim ofiarom zbrodni niemieckich i wielokrotnie mnożą liczbę żyjących ofiar, jak dowodzi tego profesor Norman Finkelstein, autor książki Holocaust Industry. Autor ten miał przykre doświadczenia w czasie dwudziestu lat pokonywania trudności w uzyskaniu odszkodowania dla swojej matki, byłej więźniarki Auschwitz.

Lekcja profesora Carpentera udzielona prezydentowi Kaczyńskiemu nie powinna nikogo dziwić. Wiadomo z historii, począwszy od starożytności, że słabsze narody nie mogą polegać na obietnicach silniejszych. Przykładem są też doświadczenia Polaków w czasach napoleońskich, kiedy przelewali krew, walcząc pod wodzą Napoleona, który cynicznie kłamał i fałszywie obiecywał, że odbuduje Polskę niepodległą. Podobnie postępują dziś USA, udzielając fałszywych gwarancji bezpieczeństwa Polsce, jak dowodzi profesor Carpenter w swoim artykule The Limits of Deterrance.

Iwo Cyprian Pogonowski

Born Sept. 3, 1921
Lwów, Poland

in Dec 1939 left Warsaw. Dec 30, 1939 arrested by Ukrainians serving the Gestapo in Dukla, then transferred to Barwinek, Krosno, Jaslo, Tarnów, Oswiecim, arrived in Oranienburg-Sachsenhausen on Aug. 10, 1940.

April 19, 1945 started on the Death March of Brandenburg from Sachsenhausen; escaped gunfire of SS-guards and arrived to Schwerin and freedom on May 2, 1945.

September 1945 arrived in Brussels, Belgium; obtained admission as a regular student at the Catholic University: Institute Superieur de Commerce, St. Ignace in Antwerp.

in 1954 graduated in Civil Engineering at the top of his class. Was invited to join honorary societies: Tau Beta Pi (general engineering honorary society), Phi Kappa Phi (academic honorary society equivalent to Phi Beta Kappa), Pi Mu (mechanical engineering honorary society), and Chi Epsilon (civil engineering honorary society). Taught descriptive geometry at the University of Tennessee;

in 1955 graduated with M.S. degree in Industrial Engineering.

in 1955 started working for Shell Oil Company in New Orleans. After one year of managerial training was assigned to design of marine structures for drilling and production of petroleum.

in 1960 started working for Texaco Research and Development in Houston, Texas as a Project Engineer. Authored total of 50 American and foreign patents on marine structures for the petroleum industry;
wrote an article: The Rise and Fall of the Polish Commonwealth - A Quest for a Representative Government in Central and Eastern Europe in the 14th to 18th Centuries. Started to work on a Tabular History of Poland.

in 1972 moved to Blacksburg, Virginia. During the following years worked as Consulting Engineer for Texaco, also taught in Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University as Adjunct Professor in the College of Civil Engineering teaching courses on marine structures of the petroleum industry. Designed and supervised the construction of a hill top home for his family, also bought 500 acre ranch (near Thomas Jefferson National Forest) where he restored 200 years old mill house on a mountain stream.

in 1978 prepared Polish-English, English-Polish Dictionary with complete phonetics, published by Hippocrene Books Inc. The dictionary included a Tabular History of Poland, Polish Language, People, and Culture as well as Pogonowski's phonetic symbols for phonetic transcriptions in English and Polish at each dictionary entry; the phonetic explanations were illustrated with cross-sections of speech (organs used to pronounce the sounds unfamiliar to the users). It was the first dictionary with phonetic transcription at each Polish entry for use by English speakers

in 1981 prepared Practical Polish-English Dictionary with complete phonetics, published by Hippocrene Books Inc.

in 1983 prepared Concise Polish-English Dictionary with complete phonetics, published by Hippocrene Books Inc. Wrote an analysis of Michael Ch ci ski's Poland, Communism, Nationalism, Anti-Semitism. Also selected crucial quotations from Norman Davies' God's Playground - A History of Poland on the subject of the Polish indigenous democratic process.

in 1985 prepared Polish-English Standard Dictionary with complete phonetics, published by Hippocrene Books Inc. Also prepared a revised and expanded edition of the Concise Polish-English Dictionary with complete phonetics, also published by Hippocrene Books Inc.

in 1987 prepared Poland: A Historical Atlas on Polish History and Prehistory including 200 maps and graphs as well as Chronology of Poland's Constitutional and Political Development, and the Evolution of Polish Identity - The Milestones. An introductory chapter was entitled Poland the Middle Ground. Aloysius A. Mazewski President of Polish-American Congress wrote an introduction. The Atlas was published by Hippocrene Books Inc. and later by Dorset Press of the Barnes and Noble Co. Inc. which sends some 30 million catalogues to American homes including color reproduction of book covers. Thus, many Americans were exposed to the cover of Pogonowski's Atlas showing the range of borders of Poland during the history - many found out for the firsttime that Poland was an important power in the past. Total of about 30,000 atlases were printed so far.

In 1988 the publication of Poland: A Historical Atlas resulted in a number of invitations extended by several Polonian organizations to Iwo Pogonowski to present Television Programs on Polish History. Pogonowski responded and produced over two year period 220 half-hour video programs in his studio at home (and at his own expense.) These programs formed a serial entitled: Poland, A History of One Thousand Years. Total of over 1000 broadcasts of these programs were transmitted by cable television in Chicago, Detroit-Hamtramck, Cleveland, and Blacksburg.

in 1990-1991 translated from the Russian the Catechism of a Revolutionary of 1869 in which crime has been treated as a normal part of the revolutionary program. Started preparation of the Killing the Best and the Brightest: A Chronology of the USSR-German Attempt to Behead the Polish Nation showing how the USSR became a prototype of modern totalitarian state, how this prototype was adapted in Germany by the Nazis.

in 1991 prepared Polish Phrasebook, Polish Conversations for Americans including picture code for gender and familiarity, published by Hippocrene Books Inc.

in 1991 prepared English Conversations for Poles with Concise Dictionary published by Hippocrene Books Inc. By then a total of over 100,000 Polish-English, English-Polish Dictionaries written by Pogonowski were sold in the United States and abroad.

in 1992 prepared a Dictionary of Polish, Latin, Hebrew, and Yiddish Terms used in Contacts between Poles and Jews. It was prepared for the history of Jews in Poland as well as 115 maps and graphs and 172 illustrations, paintings, drawings, and documents, etc. of Jewish life in Poland. This material was accompanied by proper annotations.

in 1993 prepared Jews in Poland, Rise of the Jews as a Nation from Congressus Judaicus in Poland to the Knesset in Israel, published by Hippocrene Books Inc. in 3000 copies. Foreword was written by Richard Pipes, professor of history at Harvard University, and Pogonowski's school mate in the Keczmar school in Warsaw. Part I included: a Synopsis of 1000 Year History of Jews in Poland; the 1264 Statute of Jewish Liberties in Poland in Latin and English translation; Jewish Autonomy in Poland 1264-1795; German Annihilation of the Jews. In appendixes are documents and illustrations. An Atlas is in the Part III. It is divided as follows: Early Jewish Settlements 966-1264; The Crucial 500 Years, 1264-1795; Competition (between Poles and Jews) Under Foreign Rule, 1795-1918; The Last Blossoming of Jewish Culture in Poland, 1918-1939; German Genocide of the Jews, 1940-1944; Jewish Escape from Europe 1945-1947 - The End of European (Polish) Phase of Jewish History (when most of world's Jewry lived in Europe). Pogonowski began to write a new book starting with the Chronology of the Martyrdom of Polish Intelligentsia during World War II and the Stalinist Terror; the book in preparation was entitled Killing the Best and the Brightest.

in 1995 prepared Dictionary of Polish Business, Legal and Associated Terms for use with the new edition of the Practical Polish-English, English-Polish Dictionary and later to be published as a separate book.

in 1996 Pogonowski's Poland: A Historical Atlas; was translated into Polish; some 130 of the original 200 maps printed in color; the Chronology of Poland was also translated into Polish. The Atlas was published by Wydawnictwo Suszczy ski I Baran in Kraków in 3000 copies; additional publications are expected. Prepared Polish-English, Eglish-Polish Compact Dictionary with complete phonetics, published by Hippocrene Books Inc.

in 1997 finished preparation of the Unabridged Polish-English Dictionary with complete phonetics including over 200,000 entries, in three volumes on total of 4000 pages; it is published by Hippocrene Books Inc; the Polish title is: Uniwesalny S ownik Polsko-Angielski. Besides years of work Pogonowski spent over $50,000 on computers, computer services, typing, and proof reading in order to make the 4000 page dictionary camera ready; assisted in the preparation of second edition of Jews in Poland, Rise of the Jews from Congressus Judaicus in Poland to the Knesset in Israel published in fall of 1997. Prepared computer programs for English-Polish Dictionary to serve as a companion to the Unabridged Polish-English Dictionary printed by the end of May 1997.

in 1998 Pogonowski organized preparation of CD ROM for the Unabridged Polish-English Dictionary, Practical English-Polish Dictionary, Polish Phrasebook for Tourists and Travelers to Poland, all published earlier by Iwo C. Pogonowski. The Phrasebook includes 280 minutes of bilingual audio read by actors. Started preparation for a new edition of Poland: A Historical Atlas. New Appendices are being prepared on such subjects as: Polish contribution to Allied's wartime intelligence: the breaking of the Enigma Codes, Pune Munde rocket production; Poland's contribution to the international law since 1415; Poland's early development of rocket technology such as Polish Rocketry Handbook published in 1650 in which Poles introduced for the first time into the world's literature concepts of multiple warheads, multistage rockets, new controls in rocket flight, etc. Poland's Chronology is being enlarged to reflect the mechanisms of subjugation of Polish people by the Soviet terror apparatus. Continued preparation of the Killing the Best and the Brightest: A Chronology of the USSR-German Attempt to Behead the Polish Nation, including the 1992 revelations from Soviet archives as well as the current research in Poland. Continued preparation of two-volume English Polish Dictionary, a companion to the Unabridged Polish-English Dictionary published in 1997. Reviewed Upiorna Dekada by J. T. Gross.

in 1999 Pogonowski continued writing Poland - An Illustrated History and preparing for it 21 maps and diagrams and 89 illustrations.

in 2000 Pogonowski prepared, in a camera ready form, Poland - An Illustrated History; it was published by Hippocrene Books Inc. NY 2000 and recommended by Dr. Zbigniew Brzezinski, National Security Advisor under President Carter, as "An important contribution to the better understanding of Polish history, which demonstrates in a vivid fashion the historical vicissitudes of that major European nation."

Sunday, March 1, 2009

Krakow prof। Jerzy Robert Nowak, prof। Bogusław Wolniewicz

Krakow prof। Jerzy Robert Nowak, prof। Bogusław Wolniewicz
Wykłady z Krakowaprof. Jerzy Robert Nowak, prof. Bogusław Wolniewicz (2008-06-16)Rozmowy niedokończonesłuchajzapisz